Arnold, K., and K. Zuberbühler. 2006. Semantic combinations in primate calls. Nature 441: 303.
Arnold, K., and K. Zuberbühler. 2008. Meaningful call combinations in a non-human primate. Current Biology 18: R202–R204.
Arnold, K., and K. Zuberbühler. 2012. Call combinations in monkeys: compositional or idiomatic expressions? Brain and Language 120 (3): 303–309.
Arnold, K., and K. Zuberbühler. 2013. Female putty-nosed monkeys use experimentally altered contextual information to disambiguate the cause of male alarm calls. PLoS ONE 8 (6): e65660.
Arnold, K., and D. Bar-On. 2020. Primate pragmatics, expressive behavior, and the evolution of language. Animal Behavior and Cognition 7 (2): 117–130.
Asif, N. 2022. Minimal theory of mind – a millikanian approach. Synthese 200 (2): 1–26.
Bach, K. 1997. The semantics-pragmatics distinction. Linguistische Berichte 8: 33–50.
Bach, K. 2004. Minding the gap. In The Semantics/Pragmatics distinction, ed. Claudia Bianchi. 27–43. CSLI Publications.
Bar-On, D. 2013. Origins of meaning: must we ‘go Gricean’? Mind & Language 28 (3): 342–375.
Bar-On, D. 2021. How to do things with nonwords: pragmatics, biosemantics, and origins of language in animal communication. Biology & Philosophy 36 (6): 1–25.
Bar-On, D., and R. Moore. 2017. Pragmatic interpretation and signaler-receiver asymmetries in animal communication. In The Routledge handbook of philosophy of animal minds, ed. K. Andrews and J. Beck, 291–300. Routledge.
Bermudez, J. 2003. Thinking without words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Berwick, R., and N. Chomsky. 2017. Why only us? Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Breheny, R. 2006. Communication and folk psychology. Mind & Language 21: 74–107.
Breheny, R. 2019. Scalar implicatures. In The oxford handbook of experimental semantics and pragmatics, ed. Napoleon. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Burling, R. 2005. The talking ape. New York: Oxford University Press.
Carnap, R. 1942. Introduction to semantics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Carston, R. 1998. Informativeness, relevance, and scalar implicatures. In Relevance theory, ed. R. Carston and S. Uchida. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Carston, R. 2008. Linguistic communication and the semantics/pragmatics distinction. Synthese 165: 321–345.
Carston, R. 2015. Pragmatics and semantics. In The Oxford Handbook of Pragmatics, 453–472. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Corballis, M. 2002. From Hand to Mouth: the origins of Language. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Crockford, C., et al. 2015. An intentional vocalization draws others’ attention. Animal Cognition 18 (3): 581–501.
Eckardt, W., and K. Zuberbühler. 2004. Cooperation and competition in two forest monkeys. Behavioral Ecology 15: 400–411.
Eiteljoerge, S., et al. 2018. Some pieces are missing: implicature production in children. Frontiers in Psychology 9: 1–16. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01928.
Fitch, T. 2010. The evolution of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Grice, P. 1957. Meaning. Philosophical Review 66 (3): 377–388.
Grice, P. 1968. Utterer’s meaning, sentence-meaning, and word-meaning. Foundations of Language 4: 225–242.
Heintz, C., and T. Scott-Phillips. 2022. Expression Unleashed Behavioral and Brain Sciences , vol 46
Hobaiter, K., and R. Byrne. 2014. The meanings of chimpanzee gestures. Current Biology 24 (14): 1596–1600.
Hopkins, et al. 2007. Chimpanzees differentially produce novel voclizations to capture the attention of a human. Animal Behaviour 73: 281–286.
Horn, L. 1989. A natural history of negation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hurford, J. 2007. The origins of meaning: Language in the light of evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Katsos, N., and D. Bishop. 2011. Pragmatic tolerance. Cognition 120 (1): 67–81.
Liebal, K., et al. 2004. To move or not to move: how apes adjust to the attentional state of others. Interaction Studies 5 (2): 199–219.
Maynard-Smith, J., and D. Harper. 2003. Animal signals. New York: Oxford University Press.
McNeill, D. 2012. How Language Began: gesture and Speech in Human Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Millikan, R. 1984. Language, Thought, and other Biological categories. Cambridge, Mass: The MIT Press.
Millikan, R. 1995. Pushmi-Pullyu representations. In Philosophical perspectives, ed. J. Tomberlin. vol. 9 185–200. Atascedero CA: Ridgeview Publishing.
Millikan, R. 2004. Varieties of meaning. Cambridge, Mass: The MIT Press.
Millikan, R. 2017. Beyond concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Moore, R. 2017. Convergent minds: ostension, inference and Grice’s third clause. Interface Focus 7 (3): 20160107.
Moore, R. 2018. Gricean communication, language development, and animal minds. Philosophy Compass 13 (12).
Oller, D., and U. Griebel. 2008. Evolution of communicative flexibility. Cambridge: MIT University Press.
Origgi, G., and D. Sperber. 2000. Evolution, communication, and the proper function of language. In Evolution and the human mind, ed. P. Carruthers and A. Chamberlain, 140–169. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Origgi, G., and D. Sperber. 2010. A pragmatic perspective on the evolution of language. In The Evolution of Human Language, ed. R. Larson, et al. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Recanati, F. 2002. Does linguistic communication rest on inference? Mind and Language 17: 105–126.
Recanati, F. 2004. Literal meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Recanati, F. 2010. Truth-Conditional Pragmatics. Oxford Clarendon Press.
Schel, A.M., et al. 2013. Chimpanzee alarm call production meets key criteria for intentionality. PLoS ONE 8 (10): 1–11.
Schlenker, P. 2016. The semantics-pragmatics interface. In Formal semantics, ed. M. Aloni and P. Dekker, 664–727. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Schlenker, P., et al. 2014. Monkey semantics: two “dialects” of Campbell’s monkey alarm calls. Linguistics and Philosophy 37 (6): 439–501.
Schlenker, P., et al. 2015. Pyow-hack revisited: two analyses of putty-nosed monkey alarm calls. Lingua 171: 1–23. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2015.10.002.
Schlenker, P., et al. 2016a. What do monkey calls mean? Trends in Cognitive Science 20 (12): 894–904.
Schlenker, P., et al. 2016b. Formal monkey linguistics. Theoretical Linguistics 42 (1–2): 1–90.
Scott-Phillips, T.C. 2015. Speaking our minds. London: Palgrave Macmillian.
Seyfarth, R.M., and D. Cheney. 2003. Meaning and emotion in animal vocalizations. Annals of the NY Academy of Science 1000: 32–55.
Seyfarth, R., and D. Cheney. 2017. The origin of meaning in animal signals. Animal Behavior 124: 339–346.
Sperber, D. 2000. Metarepresentation in an evolutionary perspective. In Metarepresentations: a multidisciplinary perspective, ed. D. Sperber, 117–137. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sperber, D., and D. Wilson. 2015. Beyond speaker meaning. Croatian Journal of Philosophy XV: 117–149.
Sperber, D., and D. Wilson. 1986/95. Relevance: Communication and Cognition. (2nd edition 1995.) Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Tomasello, M. 2008. Origins of human communication. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Towsend, S., et al. 2017. Exorcising Grice’s ghost: an empirical approach to studying intentional communication in animals. Biological Review 92: 1427–1433.
Vonk, J. (ed.). 2020. Animal cognition and behavior 7(2) special issue: Communication in nonhumans: the forty year anniversary of Seyfarth, Cheney and Marler.
Warren, E., and J. Call. 2022. Inferential communication: bridging the gap between intentional and ostensive communication in non-human primates. Frontiers in Psychology 14: 1–17.
Wheeler, B.C., and J. Fischer. 2012. Functionally referential signs. Evolutionary Anthropology 21 (5): 195–205. https://doi.org/10.1002/evan.21319.
Wilson, D. 2005. New directions for research on pragmatics and modularity. Lingua 115: 1129–1146.
留言 (0)